- Home
- Martha C. Nussbaum
Anger and Forgiveness
Anger and Forgiveness Read online
ANGER AND FORGIVENESS
Anger and Forgiveness
Resentment, Generosity, Justice
Martha C. Nussbaum
1
1
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries.
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America.
© Martha C. Nussbaum 2016
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction
rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above.
You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: Nussbaum, Martha Craven, 1947–
Title: Anger and forgiveness: resentment, generosity, justice /
Martha C. Nussbaum.
Description: New York: Oxford University Press, 2016. | Includes
bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2015038395| ISBN 978–0–19–933587–9 (hardcover: alk. paper) |
ISBN 978–0–19–933588–6 (ebook (updf)) | ISBN 978–0–19–933589–3 (ebook (epub)) Subjects: LCSH: Anger. | Forgiveness.
Classification: LCC BJ1535.A6 N87 2016 | DDC 179/.9—dc23 LC record available at http://lccn.loc.gov/2015038395
9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Printed by Sheridan, USA
To the memory of Bernard Williams (1929– 2003)
I agree to share a home with Pallas Athena . . .
For the city I make my prayer,
prophesying with a gentle- temper,
that the sun’s radiant beam may cause
blessings that make life flourish
to spring up in plenty from the earth.
— Aeschylus, Eumenides 916– 261
The gentle- tempered person is not vengeful, but inclined to
sympathetic understanding.
— Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1126a1– 3
We must look the world in the face with calm and clear eyes
even though the eyes of the world are bloodshot today.
— Mohandas Gandhi, August 8, 1942, reported in Jawaharlal Nehru,
The Discovery of India, ch. 1, p. 38
Contents
Acknowledgments xi
1. Introduction: Furies into Eumenides 1
2. Anger: Weakness, Payback, Down- Ranking 14
3. Forgiveness: A Genealogy 57
Appendix: Dies Irae 89
4. Intimate Relationships: The Trap of Anger 91
5. The Middle Realm: Stoicism Qualified 137
6. The Political Realm: Everyday Justice 169
7. The Political Realm: Revolutionary Justice 211
8. Conclusion: The Eyes of the World 247
Appendix A: Emotions and Upheavals of Thought 251
Appendix B: Anger and Blame 256
Appendix C: Anger and Its Species 261
Notes 265
Bibliography 293
Index 303
Acknowledgments
My first thanks are to the Sub- Faculty of Philosophy at Oxford University,
for the invitation to present the John Locke Lectures in the spring of 2014.
I am very grateful, too, to the Indian Express for an invitation to write on the theme of forgiveness apropos of Narendra Modi and the 2012 Naroda
Patiya convictions, which turned my attention to this topic and led me to
choose it as the theme of the Locke lectures— although I totally changed
my view of the topic once I began working on it. For conversations that
shaped my thinking early in the process of working on the topic, I am
grateful to Justin Coates, Saul Levmore, and Saikrishna Prakash, and for
comments on drafts of the various chapters I am grateful to Kelli Alces,
Marcia Baron, Corey Brettschneider, Thom Brooks, Daniel Brudney,
Emily Buss, David Charles, Justin Coates, Rachel Condry, Sarah Conly,
Roger Crisp, Julian Culp, John Deigh, Rosalind Dixon, David Estlund,
Jeremy Goodman, Paul Guyer, Richard Helmholz, Todd Henderson,
Aziz Huq, Terence Irwin, Will Jefferson, Sharon Krause, Alison LaCroix,
Charles Larmore, Brian Leiter, Katerina Linos, Alex Long, Jonathan
Masur, Richard McAdams, Panos Paris, Eduardo Penalver, Ariel Porat,
Eric Posner, Sara Protasi, Richard Sorabji, Nick Stephanopoulos, David
Strauss, Kevin Tobia, Jeremy Waldron, Gabrielle Watson, Laura Weinrib,
and David Weisbach. I am especially grateful to Saul Levmore for several
rounds of patient and illuminating comments. Three work- in- progress
xi
xii Acknowledgments
workshops at the University of Chicago Law School and a series of semi-
nars at Brown University were wonderful ways of getting critical com-
ments on drafts. I am grateful to Albie Sachs for illuminating discussions
about South Africa. For extremely valuable research assistance I owe
thanks to Emily Dupree, Nethanel Lipshitz, and Dasha Polzik. I would
also like to thank Emily Dupree and Nethanel Lipshitz for their help in
creating the index.
It is fitting that I dedicate this book to the memory of my teacher and
friend Bernard Williams, whose example of a life lived with daring and
integrity in philosophy matters to me more than I can say. It is perhaps
not surprising, given the nature of teacher- student relations, that I have
spent a good part of my recent career rebelling against many of the ideas
Williams conveyed in his later work. Here I find myself, somewhat sur-
prisingly to myself, drawn inexorably in a Williamsesque direction, so
to speak, recovering some of the sense of fellow feeling that I had long
ago— although I am sure Williams would find much to disagree with. It
is tragic that I cannot express those discoveries to him today.
ANGER AND FORGIVENESS
1
Introduction
Furies into Eumenides
At the end of Aeschylus’ Oresteia, two transformations take place in the archaic world of the characters, transformations that the fifth century BCE
Athenian audience would recognize as fundamentally structuring their
own world. One transformation is famous, the other often neglected.
In the famous transformation, Athena introduces legal institutions to
replace and terminate the seemingly endless cycle of blood vengeance.
Setting up a court with established procedures of reasoned argument and
the weighing of evidence, an independent third- party judge, and a jury
selected from the citizen body of Athens, she announces that blood guilt
will now be settled by law, rather than by the Furies, ancient goddesses of
revenge. But— and this is part and parcel of her famous transformation of
the Athenian community— the Furies are not simply dismissed. Instead,
Athena persuades them to join the city, giving them a place of honor
beneath the earth, in recognition of their importance for those same legal
institutions and the future health of the city.
Typically this move of Athena’s is understood to be a recognition
that the legal system must incorporate the dark vindictive passions
and honor them. Thus the great Hellenist Hugh Lloyd- Jones concludes,
“Far from wishing to abolish the prerogatives of the Erinyes, Athena is
anxious to conserve them.”1 The suggestion is that the retributive pas-
sions themselves remain unaltered; they simply have a new house built
1
2
Anger and Forgiveness
around them. They agree to accept the constraints of law, but they retain
an unchanged nature, dark and vindictive.
That reading, however, ignores the second transformation, a transfor-
mation in the nature and demeanor of the Furies themselves. At the out-
set of the trilogy’s third drama, the Furies are repulsive and horrifying.
Apollo’s Priestess, catching a glimpse of them, runs in such haste that, an
elderly woman, she falls and “runs” on all fours ( Eumenides 34– 38). They are not women but Gorgons, she exclaims. No, not even Gorgons, since
these have no wings.2 They are black, disgusting; their eyes drip a hid-
eous liquid, and they snore a fearsome blast. Their attire is totally unfit-
ting for civilized gatherings (51– 56). Shortly afterwards, Apollo depicts
them as vomiting up clots of blood that they have ingested from their
prey (183– 84). They exist, he says, only for the sake of evil (72). They
belong in some barbarian tyranny where it is customary to kill people
arbitrarily, to mutilate and torture them (185– 90).3
Nor, when they awaken, do the Furies give the lie to these grim
descriptions. As Clytemnestra’s ghost calls them, they do not speak, but
simply moan and whine: the text mentions mugmos and oigmos, noises characteristic of dogs. Their only words, as they awaken, are “get him get
him get him get him” ( labe labe etc.), as close to a doggy hunting cry as the genre allows. As Clytemnestra says: “In your dream you pursue your
prey, and you bark like a hunting dog hot on the trail of blood” (131– 32).
If the Furies are later given articulate speech, as the genre demands, we
are never to forget this initial characterization.
What Aeschylus has done here is to depict unbridled anger.4 It is
obsessive, destructive, existing only to inflict pain and ill. In its zeal for blood it is subhuman, doglike. The Greeks were far enough removed from
fancy domesticated dog breeds and close enough to raw scenes of canine
killing to associate the dog, consistently, with hideous disregard for the
victim’s pain. Even the idea of vomiting up the blood of victims is a quite
literal depiction of doggy behavior.5 The smell on the Furies’ breath is
the smell of half- digested blood, the same smell from which one might
turn in revulsion today after witnessing unbridled canine behavior.6
Apollo’s idea is that this rabid breed belongs somewhere else, in some
society that does not try to moderate cruelty or limit the arbitrary inflic-
tion of torture— surely not in a society that claims to be civilized.
Unchanged, these Furies could not be part and parcel of a working
legal system in a society committed to the rule of law.7 You don’t put wild
dogs in a cage and come out with justice. But the Furies do not make the
transition to democracy unchanged. Until quite late in the drama, they are
still their doggy selves, threatening to disgorge their venom (812), blight-
ing the land and producing infertility (812). Then, however, Athena— who
has already set up her legal institutions without them— persuades them
Introduction
3
to alter themselves so as to join her enterprise.8 “Lull to repose the bitter force of your black wave of anger,” she tells them (832– 33).9 But of course
that means a very profound transformation, indeed a virtual change of
identity, so bound up are they with anger’s obsessive force. She offers
them incentives to join the city: a place of honor beneath the earth, rever-
ence from the citizens. But the condition of this honor is that they abandon
their focus on retribution and adopt a new range of sentiments. In par-
ticular, they must adopt benevolent sentiments toward the entire city and
refrain from stirring up any trouble within it— especially not civil war,
but also not premature death or any intoxicating angry passion (850– 63).10
Indeed, they are required to invoke blessings upon the land (903 ff.). The
deal is that if they do good and have and express kindly sentiments, they
will receive good treatment and be honored. Perhaps most fundamentally
transformative of all, they must listen to the voice of persuasion (885, 970).
All of this, needless to say, is not just external containment: it is a profound inner reorientation, going to the very roots of their personality.
They accept her offer and express themselves “with a gentle- temper”
( preumenōs, 922).11 They prohibit all untimely killing (956). Each, they declare, should give love ( charmata) to each, in a “mindset of common love” ( koinophilei dianoiai, 984– 85). Once again: these sentiments are utterly foreign to their previous doggy identity. Not surprisingly,
they seem to be transformed physically in related ways. They appar-
ently assume an erect posture for the procession that concludes the
drama, and they receive crimson robes from a group of female escorts
(1028– 29)— the crimson robes that resident aliens wear in the city festival
of the Panathenaia. They have become women, rather than beasts, and
“resident aliens” in the city. Their very name is changed: they are now
The Kindly Ones (Eumenides), not The Furies.12
This second transformation is just as significant as the first, indeed
crucial to the success of the first. Aeschylus suggests that political jus-
tice does not just put a cage around anger, it fundamentally transforms
it, from something hardly human, obsessive, bloodthirsty, to something
human, accepting of reasons, calm, deliberate, and measured. Moreover,
justice focuses not on a past that can never be altered but on the creation
of future welfare and prosperity. The sense of accountability that inhabits
just institutions is, in fact, not a retributive sentiment at all, it is measured judgment in defense of current and future life. The Furies are still needed,
because this is an imperfect world and there will always be crimes to deal
with. But they are not wanted or needed in their original shape and form.
Indeed, they are not their old selves at all: they have become instruments
of justice and welfare. The city is liberated from the scourge of vindictive
anger, which produces civil strife and premature death. In the place of
anger, the city gets political justice.
4
Anger and Forgiveness
There is still room for awe: for would- be criminals and fomenters
of civil strife are on notice that bad deeds will not go unpunished. Thus,
the faces of the Eumenides are still described by Athena as fearful (99
0).
But legal accountability is not mayhem; indeed, being precisely tar-
geted, measured, and proportional, it is mayhem’s opposite. Moreover,
accountability for past acts is focused on the future: on deterrence rather
than payback.
Aeschylus is not a philosophical theorist of punishment, and he
leaves a lot of questions for later exploration. For example, is there a type of retributivism that can meet his constraints? Punishment must forgo
the lex talionis, but is there a type of retributivism that is compatible with rejecting that idea? Or must society, as Socrates and Plato believed, and
much of popular Greek thought with them, embrace an altogether differ-
ent theory of punishment, one based upon deterrence and general util-
ity?13 There are hints of the latter approach, but no clear statement.
Another liberation goes unexplored, but invites our imaginations: it
is the liberation of the private realm. In the old world of the Furies, the
family and love, familial and friendly, were burdened by the continual
need to avenge something for someone. The need for retaliation was
unending, and it shadowed all relationships, including those fundamen-
tally benign, such as Orestes’ relationship with Elektra. Revenge made
it impossible for anyone to love anyone. (The hideous musical world of
Richard Strauss’s opera Elektra is perhaps the most indelible realization of this Aeschylean/ Sophoclean insight. There’s not one note, one phrase,
that is not bent and twisted by the distorting weight of revenge.)14 But
now law takes over the task of dealing with crime, leaving the fam-
ily free to be a place of philia, of reciprocal good will. It’s not that there are no more occasions on which people are likely to feel anger: but if
they are serious, they are turned over to law, and if they are not serious,
why should they long trouble reciprocal concern? (As we shall see, that